Psychology Wiki

Assessment | Biopsychology | Comparative | Cognitive | Developmental | Language | Individual differences | Personality | Philosophy | Social |
Methods | Statistics | Clinical | Educational | Industrial | Professional items | World psychology |

Social psychology: Altruism · Attribution · Attitudes · Conformity · Discrimination · Groups · Interpersonal relations · Obedience · Prejudice · Norms · Perception · Index · Outline


Positive law (lat. ius positum) is the term generally used to describe man-made laws which bestow specific privileges upon, or remove them from, an individual or group. Etymologically the name derives from the verb to posit and is unrelated to the more common positive as not negative word usage.

The concept of positive law is distinct from "natural law", which comprises inherent rights, conferred not by act of legislation but by "God, nature or reason."[1] Positive law is also described as the law that applies at a certain time (present or past) at a certain place, consisting of statutory law, and case law as far as it is binding. More specifically, positive law may be characterized as "[l]aw actually and specifically enacted or adopted by proper authority for the government of an organized jural society."[2]

lex humana versus lex posita[]

See also: man-made law#lex humana versus lex posita

Thomas Aquinas himself conflated man-made law (lex humana) and positive law (lex posita or ius positiva).[3][4][5] However, there is a subtle distinction between them. Whereas man-made law regards law from the position of its origins (i.e. who it was that posited it), positive law regards law from the position of its legitimacy. Positive law is law by the will of whomever made it, and thus there can equally be divine positive law as there is man-made positive law. (More literally translated, lex posita is posited rather than positive law.)[3] In the Summa contra Gentiles Thomas himself writes of divine positive law where he says "si autem lex sit divinitus posita, auctoritate divina dispenatio fieri potest" (SCG, lb. 3 cap. 125).[3] Latin-English translation: "If, however, the law has been divinely placed, it can be done by divine authority."[6] Martin Luther also acknowledged the idea of divine positive law, as did Juan de Torquemada.[7]

Thomas Mackenzie divided the law into four parts, with two types of positive law: divine positive law, natural law, the positive law of independent states, and the law of nations.[8] The first, divine positive law, "concerns the duties of religion" and is derived from revelation. He contrasted it with divine natural law, which is "recognized by reason alone, without the aid of revelation".[8] The third, the positive law of independent states, is the law posited by "the supreme power in the state". It is, in other words, man-made positive law.[9]

Thomas Aquinas has little difficulty with the idea of both divine positive law and human positive law, since he places no requirements upon the person who posits law that exclude either humans or the divine.[5] However, for other philosophers the idea of both divine and human positive law has proven to be a stumbling block. Thomas Hobbes and John Austin both espoused the notion of an ultimate sovereign. Where Thomism (and indeed Mackenzie) divided sovereignty into the spiritual (God) and the temporal (Mackenzie's "supreme power in the state"), both Hobbes and Austin sought a single, undivided, sovereign as the ultimate source of the law. The problem that this causes is that a temporal sovereign cannot exist if humans are subject to a divine positive law, but if divine positive law does not apply to all humans then God cannot be sovereign either. Hobbes and Austin's answer to this is to deny the existence of divine positive law, and to invest sovereignty in humans, that are — however — subject to divine natural law. The temporal authority is sovereign, and responsible for translating divine natural law into human positive law.[10]

Government professor James Bernard Murphy of Dartmouth College explains: "although our philosophers often seek to use the term positive to demarcate specifically human law, the term and concept are not well suited to do so. All of divine law is positive in source, and much of it is positive in content […]."[5]

Legal positivism[]

This term is also sometimes used to refer to the legal philosophy legal positivism, as distinct from the schools of natural law and legal realism. In this sense, the term is often used in relation to the United States Code, portions of which restate Acts of Congress (i.e., positive law), while other portions have themselves been enacted and are thus positive law.[citation needed]

With respect to the broader sense, various philosophers have put forward theories contrasting the value of positive law relative to natural law. The normative theory of law, as put forth by the Brno school, gave pre-eminence to positive law because of its rational nature. Classical liberal and libertarian philosophers usually favor natural law over legal positivism. Positive law, to French philosopher Jean-Jacques Rousseau, was freedom from internal obstacles.[citation needed]

References[]

What supports what[]

  1. Kelsen 2007, p. 392.
  2. Black 1979.
  3. 3.0 3.1 3.2 Flannery 2001, p. 73.
  4. Voegelin 1997, p. 227–228.
  5. 5.0 5.1 5.2 Murphy 2005, p. 214.
  6. Google Translate. URL accessed on 19 June 2012.
  7. Heckel, Heckel & Krodel 2010, pp. 45,51,285.
  8. 8.0 8.1 Mackenzie 1862, p. 42.
  9. Mackenzie 1862, p. 45.
  10. Murphy 2005, p. 155–156,214.

Sources used[]

  • Kelsen, Hans (2007). General Theory of Law And State, The Lawbook Exchange.
  • Template:Cite encyclopaedia
  • Flannery, Kevin L. (2001). Acts Amid Precepts: The Logical Structure of Thomas Aquinas's Moral Theology, Continuum International Publishing Group.
  • (2010) "The Divine Positive Law" Lex charitatis: a juristic disquisition on law in the theology of Martin Luther, Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing.
  • Mackenzie, Thomas (1862). Studies in Roman law: with comparative views of the laws of France, England, and Scotland, Edinburgh: W. Blackwood and sons.
  • Murphy, James Bernard (2005). The philosophy of positive law: foundations of jurisprudence, Yale University Press.
  • Voegelin, Eric (1997). "Saint Thomas Aquinas" The collected works of Eric Voegelin, University of Missouri Press.
  • Thomas Aquinas. Summa contra Gentiles.


See also[]

Wikiquote-logo-en
Wikiquote has a collection of quotations related to:
  • Legal Naturalism
  • Man-made law
  • Natural law
  • François Gény (1861–1959), French jurist who introduced notion of "free scientific research" in positive law.
This page uses Creative Commons Licensed content from Wikipedia (view authors).